Category: Theory & Rhetoric
Summary:
Foss's work provides the foundational introduction to various theories of rhetorical criticism in a practical and useable manner that could be used by both those new to the field and those needing a refresher course. In each section she teaches the theoretical basis for a theory, then outlines the process for performing the specified criticism, how to present the results, and cautions or limitations inherent to the theory. Examples conclude each section to provide insight or potential discussion in a graduate seminar class. Very helpful for preparing works for publication that use rhetorical criticism.
Citation-worthy:
"Rhetoric is defined as the human use of symbols to communicate. This
definition includes three primary dimensions: (1) humans as the
creators of rhetoric; (2) symbols as the medium for rhetoric; and (3)
communication as the purpose for rhetoric" (Foss, 1996, p. 3).
"The standards used in rhetorical criticism to judge analyses of
artifacts are rooted in two primary assumptions. One assumption is that
objective reality does not exist. As discussed in Chapter 1, those of us
who study rhetoric believe that reality is constituted through the
rhetoric we use to talk about it; it is a symbolic creation. Thus, the
artifact you are analyzing does not constitute a reality that can be
known and proved. You cannot know what the artifact "really" means
because there are as many realities about the artifact as there are
vocabularies from which to conduct inquiry about it. A second assumption on which the standards of rhetorical criticism or
built is very much related to the first: a critic can know an artifact
only through personal interpretation of it. You cannot be objective,
impartial, and removed from the data because you bring to the critical
task particular values and experiences that are reflected in how you see
and write about an artifact. As a result of these assumptions, your task
as a critic is to offer one perspective on an artifact – one possible
way of viewing it. You are not concerned with finding the true, correct,
or right interpretation of an artifact. Consequently, two critics may analyze the same artifact, ask the same research questions, and come up with
different conclusions, and the essays they write both can be excellent
essays of criticism" (Foss, 1996, p. 17).
"Wicheln's major contribution to the development of
neo-Aristotelianismwas that he listed the topics that should be covered
in the study of a speech. A critic, he suggested, should deal with these
elements: the speaker's personality, the public character of the
speaker or the public's perception of the speaker, the audience, the
major ideas presented in the speech, the motives to which the speaker
appealed, the nature of the speaker's proofs, the speaker's judgment of
human nature in the audience, the arrangement of the speech, the
speaker's mode of expression, the speaker's method of speech
preparation, the manner of delivery, and the effect of the discourse on
the immediate audience and it's long-term effects" (Foss, 1996, pp. 21-22).
"At the same time that artifacts are functioning to provide equipment
for living for audiences, they are revealing the world view or what Burke calls deterministic screens of the rhetors who created
them" (Foss, 1996, p. 64).
"In cluster criticism, the meanings that key symbols have for a rhetor
are discovered by charting the symbols that cluster around those key
symbols in an artifact" (Foss, 1996, p. 65).
"The fantasy-theme method of rhetorical criticism, created by Ernest G.
Bormann, is designed to provide insights into the shared worldview of
groups. Impetus for the method came from the work of Robert Bales and
his associates in the study of communication in small groups. Bales
discovered the process of group fantasizing or dramatizing as a type of
communication that occurs in groups... Bormann extended the notion of
fantasizing discovered by Bales into a theory (symbolic convergence
theory) and a method (fantasy-theme criticism) that can be applied not
only to the study of small groups but also to all kinds of rhetoric in
which teams function dramatically to connect audiences with messages.…
Symbolic convergence theory is based on two major assumptions. One is that
communication creates reality. As Chapter 1 describes, reality is not
fixed but changes as our symbols for talking about it change. A second
assumption on which symbolic convergence theory is based is that symbols
not only create reality for individuals but also individuals' meanings
for symbols can converge to create a shared reality or community
consciousness" (Foss, 1996, p. 97).
"Generic criticism is rooted in the assumption that certain types of
situations provoke similar needs and expectations in audiences and thus
call for particular kinds of rhetoric. Rather than seeking to discover
how one situation affects one particular rhetorical act, the generic
critic seeks to discover commonalities in rhetorical patterns across
recurring situations. The purpose of generic criticism is to understand
rhetorical practices in different time periods and in different places
by discerning the similarities and rhetorical situations and the
rhetoric constructed in response to them—to discover "how people create
individual instances of meaning and value within structured discursive
fields." As rhetors develop messages, genres influence them to shape
their materials to create particular emphases, to generate particular
ideas, and to adopt particular personae. Similarly, audience members'
recognition of a particular artifact as belonging to a specific genre
influences their strategies of comprehension and response" (Foss, 1996, p. 137).
"Purpose in generic description is to define a genre and formulate
theoretical constructs about its characteristics. Generic description
involves four steps: (1) observing similarities in rhetorical
responses to particular situations; (2) collecting artifacts that
occur in similar situations; (3) analyzing the artifacts to discover
if they share characteristics; and (4) formulating the
organizing principle of the genre" (Foss, 1996, p. 141).
"Generic participation determines which artifacts participate in which
genres. This involves a deductive process in which you test an instance
of rhetoric against the characteristics of a genre. Generic participation
involves three steps: (1) describing the perceived situational
requirements, substantive and stylistic strategies, and organizing
principle of a genre; (2) describing the perceived situational
requirements, substantive and stylistic strategies, and organizing
principle of an artifact; and (3) comparing the characteristics of the
artifact with those of the genre to discover if the artifact belongs in
that genre" (Foss, 1996, p. 143).
"When rhetorical critics are interested in rhetoric primarily for what
it suggests about beliefs and values, their focus is on ideology. In an
ideological analysis, the critic looks beyond the surface structure of
an artifact to discover the beliefs, values, and assumptions it
suggests" (Foss, 1996, p. 209).
"In contrast to the view of metaphor as decoration, metaphor now is seen
as a major means for constituting reality. We do not perceive reality
and then interpret or give it meaning. Rather, we experience reality
through the language by which we describe it; description is the reality
we experience. Metaphor is a basic way by which the process of using
symbols to construct reality occurs. It serves as a structure in
principle, focusing on particular aspects of a phenomenon and hiding
others; thus, each metaphor produces a different description of the
"same" reality....The metaphors "we select to filter our perceptions and
organize our experience" are important because "when you choose a
metaphor you are also choosing its rules, along with the roles and
scripts that those rules dictate. Metaphors contain implicit
assumptions, points of view, and evaluations. They organize attitudes
toward whatever they describe and provide motives for acting in certain
ways.… The point is that, with the selection of a different metaphor, we
would view and experience arguments differently" (Foss, 1996, pp. 268-269).
"Narrative criticism… Narratives can be distinguished from other
rhetorical forms before characteristics. Primary defining feature of
narrative discourse is that it is comprised of at least two events.… A
second characteristic of the narrative is that the events in it are
organized by the time order. A narrative is not simply a series of events
arranged randomly – it is at least a sequence of events. The order does
not have to be chronological and may involve devices like flashbacks and
flashforwards, but at least the narrative tells in someway how the
events relate temporally to one another....A third requirement for a
narrative is that it must include some kind of causal or contributing
relationship among events in the story. Narratives depict change of some
sort, and this third requirement defines the nature of that change by stipulating the relationship between earlier and later events in the
story… A fourth requirement for a narrative is that it must be
about a unified subject… Symbols other than narratives, of course,
help us structure of the world in very much the same way that stories do.
But stories or narratives do so in a unique way. A narrative is
substantially different from a set of instructions, an argument with a
claim and evidence, definition, or contract, for example. What makes it different is that the narrative creates for both the storyteller and the audience a personal involvement in the narrated world and the active narrative" (Foss, 1996, pp. 307-308).
"Pentandic criticism is rooted in Burke's notion of dramatism, the
label Burke gives to the analysis of human motivation through terms
derived from the study of drama. Two basic assumptions underlie
dramatism. One is a language use constitutes action, not motion. Motion
corresponds to the biological or animal aspect of the human being, which
is concern with bodily processes such as growth, digestion,
respiration, and the requirements for the maintenance of those processes
— food, shelter, and rest, for example. The biological level does not
involve the use of symbols and thus is nonsymbolic.
In contrast, action corresponds to the neurological aspect of the human
being, which Burke defined as the ability of an organism to acquire
language or a symbol system. This is the realm of action or the symbolic.
Some of our motives are derived from our animality — as when we seek
food to sustain our bodies. Others, however, originate in our symbolicity, as when we strive to reach goals in arenas such as education,
politics, religion, and finance. Even our desires in such arenas arise
from our symbol system" (Foss, 1996, p. 355).
"Burke elaborates on his notion of action at the heart of dramatism by
establishing three conditions for action. One is that action must
involve freedom or choice. If we cannot make a choice, we are not acting
but are behaving mechanically… A second condition necessary for action
is purpose. Either consciously or unconsciously, we must select or will a
choice – we must choose one option over others. Motion is a third
requirement for action. While motion can exist without action (as when an
object falls, through the force of gravity, to the ground), action
cannot exist without motion. Symbolic activity or action is grounded in
the realm of the non-symbolic" (Foss, 1996, pp. 355-356).
"Most seasoned rhetorical critics, however engage in rhetorical
criticism using a different process… As useful as the formal methods of
criticism are for discovering insights into rhetoric, they do not always allow what is most interesting and significant in an artifact to be
captured and explained. In most cases, then, you want to analyze
artifacts without following any formal method of criticism. This kind of
criticism is generative in that you generate units of analysis on
explanation from your artifact rather than from previously developed,
formal methods of criticism" (Foss, 1996, p. 387).